FishingBanter

FishingBanter (http://www.fishingbanter.com/index.php)
-   Fly Fishing (http://www.fishingbanter.com/forumdisplay.php?f=6)
-   -   What's a boy to do? (http://www.fishingbanter.com/showthread.php?t=24102)

Scott Seidman November 1st, 2006 11:13 PM

What's a boy to do?
 
"riverman" wrote in news:1162253876.219819.310220
@m7g2000cwm.googlegroups.com:

Remember, we are looking at a conditional probability; dart B has
already landed farther than dart A. So our list of outcomes is limited
to:

ABC
ACB
CAB


Reducing this to a combinatorial problem is incorrect and misleading.
Each dart has a distribution around some point, hopefully the center, with
decreasing probability as you get further from the target. If darts A and
B are three or four standard deviations out, dart C has a very high
probability of being closer to the center. If A and B are a tenth of a
standard deviation out, there is a very low probability of C being closer.
We need to know the 2-D distribution of the dart C, and then we need to
know where the first two darts landed. So "not enough information" is
correct.

--
Scott
Reverse name to reply

riverman November 2nd, 2006 12:27 AM

What's a boy to do?
 

Calif Bill wrote:


You could have an almost infinite amount of darts the exact same distance
from the center. The only limiting number is how big the circle is from the
center and how big of diameter is the dart. There are an infinite number of
points equidistant from the center point. And it depends on neither the
precision or accuracy of the measurement. And in your measurement of the
distance it would be more accuracy and not precision. Precision only gives
more numbers after the decimal point.


Bill:
I'm not sure where to start, but there are a lot of little details in
your assertations that are erroneous. There's some truth also, so don't
lose hope :-)

First of all, yes the definition of a circle states there are an
infinite number of points in a plane that are equidistant from a given
point, but the liklihood of getting even two darts to land on that
circle is slim. (Just how slim is discussed in the second paragraph
below.) We don't even have to agree on how slim for now, but the the
more darts you want to have land on that circle, the less likely it is
to happen, and it approaches zero as the number of darts gets larger
and larger. Although the phrase 'almost infinite' is actually
meaningless, I assume you mean we are looking at numbers that are
growing huge beyond comprehension, so the liklihood of it happening is
shrinking tiny beyond comprehension.

Secondly, it IS a matter of precision, not accuracy. We don't care what
the actual distance from the center is, what we do care about is
whether or not two darts have the same measurement from the center,
even if that measurement is wrong. If we use an inaccurate tool, then
we might get a wrong amount (a broken ruler might show each dart to be
10.55 cm from the center, while they are both actually much less that
that). That's 'inaccurate', but if the numbers match, then we can still
assert that they are the same distance. If we use a ruler with really
fat indicator lines, we might get both measuring 10.55 cm, however if
we used a vernier caliper, calibrated or not, we might get one of them
measuring 10.550000000000001 cm and the other measuring
10.550000000000002 cm. Those are measures of high PRECISION, and my
assertation is that, no matter how the darts land, we can always use
more precise measuring devices until we find where the numbers vary.
And they always will, even if we have to go to electron microscope
levels. Just as no two snowflakes are alike, no two darts can land the
same distance from the center.

Now, I appreciate that some people might have an ingrained prejudice
against math because it doesn't always conform to their intuition (and
this might be you, or it might not). But when faced with something that
doesn't seem to 'fit' what we want to believe, there are two choices:
find out the rules of math and learn to analyze things according to
those rules, including learning the constraints and limitations and the
meaning of those, or else continue to assert that what we believe is
right because it 'feels right' to us, and use poorly structured
arguments or misnomers to claim that nothing has any validity, so we
can't possibly be wrong. That way lies madness.

--riverman


Wolfgang November 2nd, 2006 12:46 AM

What's a boy to do?
 

Scott Seidman wrote:
...Each dart has a distribution around some point, hopefully the center, with
decreasing probability as you get further from the target.


I detect a troublesome ambiguity here. I see two ways to read this
without the reader doing any violence to good sense:

1. Each dart has a distribution around some point, hopefully the
center, with decreasing probability of being close to the center as the
thrower gets further from the target.

2. Each dart has a distribution around some point, hopefully the
center, with decreasing probability of landing at any point as distance
from the center increases.

I think no one will have much trouble with the first reading. The
second is easier to defend than it may appear at a glance because it
is.....partly.....true. I assume that a truly great dart thower can
consistently place the darts very close to the center of the board
(which, as we all know is not necessarily the object in every game, but
is as good a spot as any other and does, at any rate, appear to be
accepted for the purposes of this discussion) and I know that there are
people whose skills are so abysmal that they rarely hit the board at
all from the standard distance of what I believe to be 8 feet or so.
Probabilities of distribution clearly vary widely (if not to say
wildly) between these two extremes. What makes the second reading
defensible is that for the best dart throwers the probability of
landing at a given point DOES decrease with distance from the
center.....um.....mostly. In fact, it also decreases as the point gets
very very close to a precisely measured center. The same is also true
for ALL dart throwers. The difference among them is that the diameter
of the circle at which increasing or decreasing probabilities converge
or diverge (depending on direction of travel toward or away from the
circle) varies with the skill of the thrower, being very small for the
very good and very large for the very bad.

I haven't looked at this, or the larger discussion, closely enough to
suppose that it will be a crushing blow to anyone's thesis but, on the
other hand, I haven't seen anything yet that I think rules it out
either. It may not even be relevant or interesting given the
assumptions that have been (if only tacitly) agreed on.

However, it does once again open the door to an examination of those
assumptions. Given that no one showed any interest the first time I
brought the matter up though, I guess I won't go into it in any depth
here. I will simply confine myself to making a proposition open to
anyone. Give me three darts and a prediction of where they will land
relative to one another in terms of distance from the center of the
target, and I will prove you wrong EVERY time. :)

Wolfgang


riverman November 2nd, 2006 12:53 AM

What's a boy to do?
 

Jonathan Cook wrote:
riverman wrote:

solution. To answer the darts question, merely rely on the definition
of probablilty: the number of ways to achieve your objective, divided
by the number of possible outcomes. List all the possible arrangements
of how the darts could land, and count how many fit our scenario.


I saw your response to my post, but I still disagree. You are making
all sorts of assumptions by reducing it to this simple model, not
the least of which is some sort of uniform probability distribution,
or worse yet, a 50-50 likelihood of landing inside or outside of
dart A. And those assumptions _heavily_ depend on how closely dart
A is to the target, among other things (like if I'm throwing, who
has very little dart-throwing experience). Dart throwing is _nothing_
like dice rolling...

First, list all the ways to throw three darts, A B and C.


ABC
ACB
BAC
BCA
CAB
CBA


Sometime too simple _is_ too simple...

But, Wolfgang's original post has got me thinking, and I'd be interested
to see your response to a post I'm about to make from his original
question (and Wolfgang's and any others' responses, too.)

Jon.


Hi Jon:
Actually, I'm not assuming a uniform distribution, just an unchanging
one. I think the only crucial assumption here (beyond the obvious ones:
gravity is constant, the target is planar, the darts are self-similar,
the wind doesn't change, etc) is that the skill of the thrower does not
improve or deteriorate demonstrably between throws, and that the
thrower is aiming for the same spot with each throw.

Some people are NOT assuming these things, and I agree that it skews
the results, and I'll acquiesce and say that I should have stated those
things and not assumed them. The nonsense about two darts being able to
be equidistant is just that: nonsense. But if we assume the conditions
are identical for all three darts, then each throw is identical without
prejudice, and the six outcomes are equally likely, and the answer is
2/3.

Take this problem across the hall to the Stats professors and see what
they have to say about it.

Your other assertations about probabilities not being meaningful in the
context of singular events sounds bizarre. I'll re-read what you wrote,
mostly because I see you have some education in math and statistics,
but it sounds like you are getting twisted around somewhere. Possibly
within the definition of 'probability'.

--riverman


Wolfgang November 2nd, 2006 01:30 AM

What's a boy to do?
 

riverman wrote:
....If we use a ruler with really
fat indicator lines, we might get both measuring 10.55 cm, however if
we used a vernier caliper, calibrated or not, we might get one of them
measuring 10.550000000000001 cm and the other measuring
10.550000000000002 cm. Those are measures of high PRECISION, and my
assertation is that, no matter how the darts land, we can always use
more precise measuring devices until we find where the numbers vary....


If you can REALLY measure things on a scale several orders of magnitude
short of an angstrom, I REALLY wanna come play in your shop! :)

For the benefit of those who don't know what a vernier caliper is (a
friend of mine....who should have known better.....once thought a
micrometer I handed him was some sort of special application c-clamp
and proceeded to see how tight he could crank it.....I nearly smacked
his ****in' hea......well, never mind about that), suffice it to say
that the numbers displayed above were used for effect but Myron's point
is indisputable. Precision measuring instruments these days are such
that finding two darts whose distance from a given point is so close
that the difference can't be measured is vanishingly small. The REAL
difficulty (whether in a pub or a laboratory) would be in getting
agreement on exactly where to measure from.

Wolfgang


Calif Bill November 2nd, 2006 01:39 AM

What's a boy to do?
 

"riverman" wrote in message
oups.com...

Calif Bill wrote:


You could have an almost infinite amount of darts the exact same distance
from the center. The only limiting number is how big the circle is from
the
center and how big of diameter is the dart. There are an infinite number
of
points equidistant from the center point. And it depends on neither the
precision or accuracy of the measurement. And in your measurement of the
distance it would be more accuracy and not precision. Precision only
gives
more numbers after the decimal point.


Bill:
I'm not sure where to start, but there are a lot of little details in
your assertations that are erroneous. There's some truth also, so don't
lose hope :-)

First of all, yes the definition of a circle states there are an
infinite number of points in a plane that are equidistant from a given
point, but the liklihood of getting even two darts to land on that
circle is slim. (Just how slim is discussed in the second paragraph
below.) We don't even have to agree on how slim for now, but the the
more darts you want to have land on that circle, the less likely it is
to happen, and it approaches zero as the number of darts gets larger
and larger. Although the phrase 'almost infinite' is actually
meaningless, I assume you mean we are looking at numbers that are
growing huge beyond comprehension, so the liklihood of it happening is
shrinking tiny beyond comprehension.

Secondly, it IS a matter of precision, not accuracy. We don't care what
the actual distance from the center is, what we do care about is
whether or not two darts have the same measurement from the center,
even if that measurement is wrong. If we use an inaccurate tool, then
we might get a wrong amount (a broken ruler might show each dart to be
10.55 cm from the center, while they are both actually much less that
that). That's 'inaccurate', but if the numbers match, then we can still
assert that they are the same distance. If we use a ruler with really
fat indicator lines, we might get both measuring 10.55 cm, however if
we used a vernier caliper, calibrated or not, we might get one of them
measuring 10.550000000000001 cm and the other measuring
10.550000000000002 cm. Those are measures of high PRECISION, and my
assertation is that, no matter how the darts land, we can always use
more precise measuring devices until we find where the numbers vary.
And they always will, even if we have to go to electron microscope
levels. Just as no two snowflakes are alike, no two darts can land the
same distance from the center.

Now, I appreciate that some people might have an ingrained prejudice
against math because it doesn't always conform to their intuition (and
this might be you, or it might not). But when faced with something that
doesn't seem to 'fit' what we want to believe, there are two choices:
find out the rules of math and learn to analyze things according to
those rules, including learning the constraints and limitations and the
meaning of those, or else continue to assert that what we believe is
right because it 'feels right' to us, and use poorly structured
arguments or misnomers to claim that nothing has any validity, so we
can't possibly be wrong. That way lies madness.

--riverman


Your statement was no two darts could land equidistant from the center. As
I state, totally wrong. There is an infinite number of points on the circle
where the first dart landed from the center. You change the statement to
say the more darts that are thrown, the likelihood that two are equidistant
from the center diminishes. The more darts tossed the greater the
likelihood two are equidistant. Not all equidistant, but two can be. Sure,
your vernier calipers can have more precision than a wooden school rule, but
it is still the accuracy of the measurement. Your statement is akin to
saying you have increased precision when you multiply 1.02 times 2.04 and
get 2.0808. You still have only 2 decimal points of precision. As to using
an accurate tool, does not need to be. The actual measurement may be wrong,
but as long as the measurement is the same is all we need to know for the
stated question. As long as the precision and accuracy is great enough in
the measuring instrument to have repeatability, the actual distance matters
not.

Maybe you should go back and review the rules of math. And review your
arguments.



riverman November 2nd, 2006 04:04 AM

What's a boy to do?
 

Scott Seidman wrote:
"riverman" wrote in news:1162253876.219819.310220
@m7g2000cwm.googlegroups.com:

Remember, we are looking at a conditional probability; dart B has
already landed farther than dart A. So our list of outcomes is limited
to:

ABC
ACB
CAB


Reducing this to a combinatorial problem is incorrect and misleading.
Each dart has a distribution around some point, hopefully the center, with
decreasing probability as you get further from the target. If darts A and
B are three or four standard deviations out, dart C has a very high
probability of being closer to the center. If A and B are a tenth of a
standard deviation out, there is a very low probability of C being closer.
We need to know the 2-D distribution of the dart C, and then we need to
know where the first two darts landed. So "not enough information" is
correct.


But consider that outcome of throwing each dart is independant. IOW,
there will always be one dart that is closest, one that is farthest,
one that is in between. The combinatoric arrangement merely gives all
the arrangements.

Yes, if Dart A is very very close, then the probability of dart B being
closer gets smaller. But that same distribution gets repeated again
with dart B being closer than A if we throw dart B first. So, unless
the ability of the thrower changes between the two darts, AB is
identical to BA.

--riverman


Kevin Vang November 2nd, 2006 05:21 AM

What's a boy to do?
 
In article t,
says...
Your statement was no two darts could land equidistant from the center. As
I state, totally wrong.


Two darts could conceivable land equidistant from the center; however,
the probability of that happening is 0. Explaining why will require a
bit of less than elementary probability theory, with integral calculus
as a prerequisite. We can go there, if you are up to it...

Kevin

Calif Bill November 2nd, 2006 05:53 AM

What's a boy to do?
 

"Kevin Vang" wrote in message
t...
In article t,
says...
Your statement was no two darts could land equidistant from the center.
As
I state, totally wrong.


Two darts could conceivable land equidistant from the center; however,
the probability of that happening is 0. Explaining why will require a
bit of less than elementary probability theory, with integral calculus
as a prerequisite. We can go there, if you are up to it...

Kevin


Explain why could not happen.



riverman November 2nd, 2006 08:21 AM

What's a boy to do?
 

Calif Bill wrote:
"Kevin Vang" wrote in message
t...
In article t,
says...
Your statement was no two darts could land equidistant from the center.
As
I state, totally wrong.


Two darts could conceivable land equidistant from the center; however,
the probability of that happening is 0. Explaining why will require a
bit of less than elementary probability theory, with integral calculus
as a prerequisite. We can go there, if you are up to it...

Kevin


Explain why could not happen.


I don't know if you have taken Integral Calculus, so I won't use that
to explain it. The simplest 'geometrically appealing' explanation is to
say that the probability of hitting some target is directly related to
the size of the target. The bigger the spot you are trying to hit, the
more likely it is to hit it.

Now, if you are aiming for a curved line....specifically the line that
describes a circle, you have to consider the width of that line. Since
circles are a collection of points, and points have no width, then you
are essentially aiming for something that has a width of zero. Which
means the possibility of hitting it is zero.

You can hit it ONCE, because its position is unknown until the first
dart actually lands. Once that dart establishes the position of the
circle, it becomes a target of width zero which another dart cannot
possibly hit. You can reduce the size of your miss (lets call it your
'slop') to be as small as you want by making less and less precise
measurements, but the converse is also true...you can always find the
slop by increasing the precision of your measurement. You cannot
eliminate the slop; you cannot ever hit the line.: its a matter of
precision. Just like no two snowflakes are alike.

Throwing more and more darts DOES increase the liklihood of hitting
something more than once, but if the liklihood of hitting it is already
infinitely small; throwing more and more darts doesn't make it any more
likely. Throwing infinite darts creates what is called an
'indeterminate' form, and we cannot solve it that way. We get an
infinitely large number of opportunities of achieving something that
has an infinitely small chance of happening. Its incorrect to conclude
that it will happen infinite times....Infinity x (1/infinity) does not
equal infinity. It doesn't equal, or mean, anything.

However, throwing a FINITE number of darts....say two, at something
that we have an infintely small chance of hitting IS solvable. Its
three times 'infinitely small', which is still 'infinitely small'. If
you have taken any calculus, you know the value of 'infintely small' is
zero.

--riverman


Stan Gula November 2nd, 2006 11:06 AM

What's a boy to do?
 
"Kevin Vang" wrote:
Two darts could conceivable land equidistant from the center; however,
the probability of that happening is 0. Explaining why will require a
bit of less than elementary probability theory, with integral calculus
as a prerequisite. We can go there, if you are up to it...

Kevin


I was wondering when you would pop up. We could let it go with an "It's
intuitively obvious and not important in solving the problem at hand". In
practice, we're talking about physical objects which are not made up of
infinitesimal particles, but a finite set of rather large (relatively)
molecules of stuff, so the set of positions where a dart could penetrate is
a very small subset (albeit a very large set) of the set of points on a
circle through the location of any dart. In practice, I would prefer to
find an approximation to the solution through Monte Carlo simulation (with
real darts, not a computer model), accompanied by large quantities of
fermented malt. In which case I'd hazard (hah!) a guess that the
probability approaches 1 as the amount of malt consumed approaches
unconsciousness.

--
Stan
from the applied side.



Scott Seidman November 2nd, 2006 12:37 PM

What's a boy to do?
 
"riverman" wrote in news:1162440298.459352.48600
@e3g2000cwe.googlegroups.com:

The combinatoric arrangement merely gives all
the arrangements.


Yes, and has next to nothing to do with the probability of any outcomes.

In five years, there are two possible outcomes to the experiment "Who has
more money, me, or Donald Trump". I could have more money, or he can have
more money. By your logic, I therefore have a 50% chance of having more
money than The Donald. Good to know.

--
Scott
Reverse name to reply

riverman November 2nd, 2006 12:41 PM

What's a boy to do?
 

"Stan Gula" wrote in message
news:Fik2h.10075$gf5.7278@trndny01...
"Kevin Vang" wrote:
Two darts could conceivable land equidistant from the center; however,
the probability of that happening is 0. Explaining why will require a
bit of less than elementary probability theory, with integral calculus
as a prerequisite. We can go there, if you are up to it...

Kevin


I was wondering when you would pop up. We could let it go with an "It's
intuitively obvious and not important in solving the problem at hand". In
practice, we're talking about physical objects which are not made up of
infinitesimal particles, but a finite set of rather large (relatively)
molecules of stuff, so the set of positions where a dart could penetrate
is a very small subset (albeit a very large set) of the set of points on a
circle through the location of any dart. In practice, I would prefer to
find an approximation to the solution through Monte Carlo simulation (with
real darts, not a computer model), accompanied by large quantities of
fermented malt. In which case I'd hazard (hah!) a guess that the
probability approaches 1 as the amount of malt consumed approaches
unconsciousness.

--
Stan
from the applied side.


I concur. But I was also about to propose to Jon (who IS a computer geek) to
write a computer simulation and run it a few hundred million times.

--riverman



Charlie Choc November 2nd, 2006 12:45 PM

What's a boy to do?
 
On 2 Nov 2006 12:37:19 GMT, Scott Seidman wrote:

"riverman" wrote in news:1162440298.459352.48600
:

The combinatoric arrangement merely gives all
the arrangements.


Yes, and has next to nothing to do with the probability of any outcomes.

In five years, there are two possible outcomes to the experiment "Who has
more money, me, or Donald Trump". I could have more money, or he can have
more money. By your logic, I therefore have a 50% chance of having more
money than The Donald. Good to know.


You might as well run for president, too. You have a 50% chance of being
elected.
--
Charlie...
http://www.chocphoto.com

riverman November 2nd, 2006 12:58 PM

What's a boy to do?
 

"Scott Seidman" wrote in message
. 1.4...
"riverman" wrote in news:1162440298.459352.48600
@e3g2000cwe.googlegroups.com:

The combinatoric arrangement merely gives all
the arrangements.


Yes, and has next to nothing to do with the probability of any outcomes.

In five years, there are two possible outcomes to the experiment "Who has
more money, me, or Donald Trump". I could have more money, or he can have
more money. By your logic, I therefore have a 50% chance of having more
money than The Donald. Good to know.


That's a seriously lame strawman argument.

Speaking of straws....put three straws in your hand...one short, one medium,
one long. What's the probability of drawing the shortest one last?

And what's the probability of drawing the longest one first, and the
shortest one after that?

--riverman



Scott Seidman November 2nd, 2006 01:19 PM

What's a boy to do?
 
"riverman" wrote in :

And what's the probability of drawing the longest one first, and the
shortest one after that?

--riverman



Yes, that problem is a matter of combinatorials, but that isn't the
problem you posed.

You toss three darts at a target. Dart A misses the target, then Dart
B
misses by even more. What is the probability that Dart C will miss by
more than Dart A?


I just need to know the distribution of dart C, and the location of Dart
A. I don't even care if darts A,B, and C are independent. It is not a
combinatorial problem. If dart A is 1mm from the target, the probability
is very good that dart C will miss by more. If dart A is a mile from the
target, the probability is very poor.

You could ask your question in a different way, to get the answer you
want, which is "you are going to throw three darts at a target. What is
the probability that the third dart will miss by more than the first
dart?" This is a VERY different question, but the answer is the one you
are describing.


--
Scott
Reverse name to reply

Scott Seidman November 2nd, 2006 01:24 PM

What's a boy to do?
 
Scott Seidman wrote in
. 1.4:

If dart A is 1mm from the target, the probability
is very good that dart C will miss by more. If dart A is a mile from
the target, the probability is very poor.


To express this better, the location of the dart is a continuous random
variable, but you aren't treating it that way.


--
Scott
Reverse name to reply

riverman November 2nd, 2006 01:29 PM

What's a boy to do?
 

"Scott Seidman" wrote in message
. 1.4...
"riverman" wrote in :

And what's the probability of drawing the longest one first, and the
shortest one after that?

--riverman



Yes, that problem is a matter of combinatorials, but that isn't the
problem you posed.

You toss three darts at a target. Dart A misses the target, then Dart
B
misses by even more. What is the probability that Dart C will miss by
more than Dart A?


I just need to know the distribution of dart C, and the location of Dart
A. I don't even care if darts A,B, and C are independent. It is not a
combinatorial problem. If dart A is 1mm from the target, the probability
is very good that dart C will miss by more. If dart A is a mile from the
target, the probability is very poor.


You're getting close. Considering that dart A and dart C have the same
distribution, then either dart can occupy whatever spot the other dart
occupies (minus the situation where they occupy the same point). As you
said, the probability changes according to the location of dart A. Whatever
high probability exists if A is close is countered by the low probability if
A is far.

Thus, all the possible positions of A and C equal all the possible positions
of C and A....its a combinatoric problem. Specifically because I DON'T
give the position of dart A.

If its any comfort, I'm not making this problem up.

--riverman



Joe McIntosh November 2nd, 2006 01:37 PM

choc tr
 

"Charlie Choc" wrote in message -- joe
responds

glad to see you returned --don"t we get a trip report about your western
summer? even if no fishing is included--most of the messages here do not.

spent a couple of day in Graham co last week with Jeff----then Dene and I
spent a week bumming around snowbird area--one big rain so tried to improve
my nymphing ability with slight success, but did dig out one big rainbow in
big pool just upstream from snowbird cabin. They call them steelhead up that
way as they come into streams from lakes to lay eggs.

Went to eye doctor yesterday and after he said I was still 20/20 I
explained that tennis balls I once returned now go flying by, and Jeff had
to tie on small flies for me. Dr said perhaps I need to clean my glasses and
gave me a bill for $121

Kayaking in backwater salt most every day--not catching much but just
cannot say inside and do homework when Carolina in Oct is smiling

Indian Joe




Scott Seidman November 2nd, 2006 01:51 PM

What's a boy to do?
 
"riverman" wrote in :

Thus, all the possible positions of A and C equal all the possible
positions of C and A...



But the question as you pose it has nothing to do with all the possible
positions of dart A-- it has to do with one specific position of dart A!
Let's say that A is 5cm away. Then you are looking for p(C5), which has
a value that depends only on the distribution of dart C.

Whatever high probability exists if A is close is
countered by the low probability if A is far.


True before dart A is thrown, but not after dart A is thrown. Now, you
have a real honest to goodness value for dart A.


Thus, all the possible positions of A and C equal all the possible

positions
of C and A....its a combinatoric problem. Specifically because I
DON'T give the position of dart A.


This doesn't mean that you can just ignore the fact that Dart A is stuck
at a precise location in the dartboard, and it's why there isn't enough
info to offer a p-value.

If its any comfort, I'm not making this problem up.


Then the person who did got it wrong.

--
Scott
Reverse name to reply

Charlie Choc November 2nd, 2006 02:19 PM

choc tr
 
On Thu, 02 Nov 2006 13:37:57 GMT, "Joe McIntosh"
wrote:


"Charlie Choc" wrote in message -- joe
responds

glad to see you returned --don"t we get a trip report about your western
summer? even if no fishing is included--most of the messages here do not.

I took a lot of pictures and helped build some houses, went to a pow-wow and
rodeo, and generally had a ball, although 8 weeks is plenty long enough to sleep
in what amounts to a tent with wheels.

As for the fishing part, I floated the Bighorn and Yellowstone with 'Bouncer'
and we had a fine time and caught some nice fish. I also fished in Yellowstone,
but water was low and the streams were crowded - especially the Firehole and in
Lamar Valley. The park seemed more crowded the 1st 2 weeks of September than it
has been in July, and that combined with the rutting elk and bison make for some
dangerous encounters. Several people were hospitalized while I was there, mostly
by virtue of getting too close to bull elk. My best 'catching' was probably in
Grand Teton and just outside it on the Gros Ventre and the Snake. Not as many
fishermen down there but the place was thick with photographers, and you had to
be careful and stay away from the rutting moose by the rivers.
--
Charlie...
http://www.chocphoto.com

riverman November 2nd, 2006 02:23 PM

What's a boy to do?
 

"Scott Seidman" wrote in message
. 1.4...
"riverman" wrote in :

Thus, all the possible positions of A and C equal all the possible
positions of C and A...



But the question as you pose it has nothing to do with all the possible
positions of dart A-- it has to do with one specific position of dart A!
Let's say that A is 5cm away. Then you are looking for p(C5), which has
a value that depends only on the distribution of dart C.

Whatever high probability exists if A is close is
countered by the low probability if A is far.


True before dart A is thrown, but not after dart A is thrown. Now, you
have a real honest to goodness value for dart A.


Yes, but the possbilities for the value for A are limitless. You cannot
calculate all the different arrangements. Remember, the original question
did not specify where A landed, only that it did.


Thus, all the possible positions of A and C equal all the possible

positions
of C and A....its a combinatoric problem. Specifically because I
DON'T give the position of dart A.


This doesn't mean that you can just ignore the fact that Dart A is stuck
at a precise location in the dartboard, and it's why there isn't enough
info to offer a p-value.


No its not. Its stuck in any of an infinite number of locations. Each one
has a different effect on the probability of B being closer.


If its any comfort, I'm not making this problem up.


Then the person who did got it wrong.


Well, here's the results of one person who ran 1 million trials each, using
uniform, normal, gaussian and random distributions.
http://www.gatago.com/rec/puzzles/25594126.html

He came up with 2/3 every time. I just have an aversion to Monte Carlo
methods, but go ahead and try it yourself and let us know what the result
is.

--riverman



Wolfgang November 2nd, 2006 02:47 PM

What's a boy to do?
 

"Stan Gula" wrote in message
news:Fik2h.10075$gf5.7278@trndny01...
...In practice, I would prefer to find an approximation to the solution
through Monte Carlo simulation (with real darts, not a computer model),
accompanied by large quantities of fermented malt. In which case I'd
hazard (hah!) a guess that the probability approaches 1 as the amount of
malt consumed approaches unconsciousness.


All well and good as a purely intellectual exercise but in real world
situations one cannot afford a cavalier disregard (such as you have
demonstrated here) for the effects of important variables like (in this
instance) time. If the probability's approach to 1 is proportional to the
approach of looming unconsciousness (a proposition I am not prepared to
contest) it may nevertheless prove to be chimerical, depending, obviously,
on whether or not (and, if so, when) the blessed union with the cosmic
consciousness occurs. This, in turn, is a function of rate of consumption
over time.*

Wolfgang
*precise analyses do, of course, also depend on mitigating factors like body
mass, whether the malt is consumed in a raw or distilled form, etc., but
these details need not concern us here as they can (and, indeed, must) be
determined empirically in each experimental run.



[email protected] November 2nd, 2006 02:50 PM

What's a boy to do?
 
On 1 Nov 2006 16:27:51 -0800, "riverman" wrote:


Calif Bill wrote:


You could have an almost infinite amount of darts the exact same distance
from the center. The only limiting number is how big the circle is from the
center and how big of diameter is the dart. There are an infinite number of
points equidistant from the center point. And it depends on neither the
precision or accuracy of the measurement. And in your measurement of the
distance it would be more accuracy and not precision. Precision only gives
more numbers after the decimal point.


Bill:
I'm not sure where to start, but there are a lot of little details in
your assertations that are erroneous. There's some truth also, so don't
lose hope :-)

First of all, yes the definition of a circle states there are an
infinite number of points in a plane that are equidistant from a given
point, but the liklihood of getting even two darts to land on that
circle is slim. (Just how slim is discussed in the second paragraph
below.) We don't even have to agree on how slim for now, but the the
more darts you want to have land on that circle, the less likely it is
to happen, and it approaches zero as the number of darts gets larger
and larger. Although the phrase 'almost infinite' is actually
meaningless, I assume you mean we are looking at numbers that are
growing huge beyond comprehension, so the liklihood of it happening is
shrinking tiny beyond comprehension.

Secondly, it IS a matter of precision, not accuracy. We don't care what
the actual distance from the center is, what we do care about is
whether or not two darts have the same measurement from the center,
even if that measurement is wrong. If we use an inaccurate tool, then
we might get a wrong amount (a broken ruler might show each dart to be
10.55 cm from the center, while they are both actually much less that
that). That's 'inaccurate', but if the numbers match, then we can still
assert that they are the same distance. If we use a ruler with really
fat indicator lines, we might get both measuring 10.55 cm, however if
we used a vernier caliper, calibrated or not, we might get one of them
measuring 10.550000000000001 cm and the other measuring
10.550000000000002 cm. Those are measures of high PRECISION, and my
assertation is that, no matter how the darts land, we can always use
more precise measuring devices until we find where the numbers vary.
And they always will, even if we have to go to electron microscope
levels. Just as no two snowflakes are alike, no two darts can land the
same distance from the center.

Now, I appreciate that some people might have an ingrained prejudice
against math because it doesn't always conform to their intuition (and
this might be you, or it might not). But when faced with something that
doesn't seem to 'fit' what we want to believe, there are two choices:
find out the rules of math and learn to analyze things according to
those rules, including learning the constraints and limitations and the
meaning of those, or else continue to assert that what we believe is
right because it 'feels right' to us, and use poorly structured
arguments or misnomers to claim that nothing has any validity, so we
can't possibly be wrong. That way lies madness.

--riverman


Whether or not _you_ can measure to _your_ satisfaction that two points
on a 2-dimensional plane are _absolutely_ the same distance from an
initially-chosen point (in this case, a "target"_), those two points
certainly exist. The random selection of a second point (the landing of
Dart A) "x" distance from the first point (the "target") creates a
radius from which a circumference may be scribed. The second dart (Dart
B) and its landing point have no relevance and can be ignored. A third
dart is thrown (Dart C). According to your theory, that dart can easily
and readily strike any point on the disk or any point outside of the
circumference created by the selection of the first and second points,
up to and including "un-measurably" close to the inside or the outside
of the circumference, but can never actually strike a point on the
circumference. IOW, the third point (Dart C) can only create a second
radius that must be less than or greater than the first radius. With
not being able to select a second point on the circumference, arcs, in
such a world, don't exist. If arcs don't exist, geometry, trig, etc.
begins to break down. In the failure cascade of interrelated bits , it
takes all math down with it. Congratulations, you've talked your way
out of a fairly decent, secure job...yep, you're a Democrat...ah, well,
perhaps there's a job on Kerry's staff for ya...

On the practical side, it seems rather curious that you can measure to
your own satisfaction that it isn't the same distance, yet you cannot
measure to your satisfaction that it is the same distance.

HTH,
R

Wolfgang November 2nd, 2006 03:06 PM

What's a boy to do?
 

wrote in message
...


Whether or not _you_ can measure to _your_ satisfaction that two points
on a 2-dimensional plane are _absolutely_ the same distance from an
initially-chosen point (in this case, a "target"_), those two points
certainly exist. The random selection of a second point (the landing of
Dart A) "x" distance from the first point (the "target") creates a
radius from which a circumference may be scribed. The second dart (Dart
B) and its landing point have no relevance and can be ignored. A third
dart is thrown (Dart C). According to your theory, that dart can easily
and readily strike any point on the disk or any point outside of the
circumference created by the selection of the first and second points,
up to and including "un-measurably" close to the inside or the outside
of the circumference, but can never actually strike a point on the
circumference. IOW, the third point (Dart C) can only create a second
radius that must be less than or greater than the first radius. With
not being able to select a second point on the circumference, arcs, in
such a world, don't exist. If arcs don't exist, geometry, trig, etc.
begins to break down. In the failure cascade of interrelated bits , it
takes all math down with it. Congratulations, you've talked your way
out of a fairly decent, secure job...yep, you're a Democrat...ah, well,
perhaps there's a job on Kerry's staff for ya...

On the practical side, it seems rather curious that you can measure to
your own satisfaction that it isn't the same distance, yet you cannot
measure to your satisfaction that it is the same distance.


Thus forcing one to conclude that forty bucks worth does not constitute an
"expensive education" so much as it does outright robbery.

Wolfgang
on the other hand, given what we get here for free, forty bucks worth of
entertainment would almost certainly kill any mere mortal. :)



[email protected] November 2nd, 2006 03:18 PM

What's a boy to do?
 
On 1 Nov 2006 16:46:23 -0800, "Wolfgang" wrote:

SNI-I-I-I-IP

I will simply confine myself


Well, no, you didn't do either, but perhaps you should...

to making a proposition open to
anyone. Give me three darts and a prediction of where they will land
relative to one another in terms of distance from the center of the
target, and I will prove you wrong EVERY time. :)


Gee, it seems like this might be an attempt at a sucker bet...OK. I
accept. And I'd offer that you couldn't even do it ONE time... and that
you couldn't do it even if given a 3-dimensional "dartboard"...but don't
pee all over yourself, here's another hint: the taxpayers of Olathe,
Kansas are probably very glad you can't do it even that one time...why,
heck, one might say that's the essence of an industry...

HTH,
R
....I feel generous, here's another hint: ya better go back to sucker-bet
development school - with the "bet" above, it doesn't matter how, when,
or if you throw them...

Wolfgang


riverman November 2nd, 2006 03:37 PM

What's a boy to do?
 

wrote in message
...
On 1 Nov 2006 16:27:51 -0800, "riverman" wrote:


Whether or not _you_ can measure to _your_ satisfaction that two points
on a 2-dimensional plane are _absolutely_ the same distance from an
initially-chosen point (in this case, a "target"_), those two points
certainly exist.


Yes, they do.

The random selection of a second point (the landing of
Dart A) "x" distance from the first point (the "target") creates a
radius from which a circumference may be scribed. The second dart (Dart
B) and its landing point have no relevance and can be ignored.


Not necessarily, it depends on what is being asked. "Conditional
probabilities" do exist. But in the case of what you are discussing (the
existance of arcs), I concur; we can ignore the second dart for now.

A third
dart is thrown (Dart C). According to your theory, that dart can easily
and readily strike any point on the disk or any point outside of the
circumference created by the selection of the first and second points,
up to and including "un-measurably" close to the inside or the outside
of the circumference, but can never actually strike a point on the
circumference. IOW, the third point (Dart C) can only create a second
radius that must be less than or greater than the first radius.


Yes, that's correct also. There is a statement in calculus that asserts that
no matter what two numbers you choose on the number line, there is always
another number between them. No matter how close to the circumference you
get, you can always get closer. But you cannot get there unless you, well,
get there.

With
not being able to select a second point on the circumference, arcs, in
such a world, don't exist.


No one said you cannot select a second point. What is being said is that the
probability of another dart hitting that point, or any other point on that
circle, is zero. Thats because the point is infinitely small. The
probability of hitting something infinitely small is infinitely
small....zero, in fact.

If arcs don't exist,


....and everything after this antecedant is YOUR proposition, since I know
they do exist.

geometry, trig, etc.
begins to break down. In the failure cascade of interrelated bits , it
takes all math down with it. Congratulations, you've talked your way
out of a fairly decent, secure job...yep, you're a Democrat...ah, well,
perhaps there's a job on Kerry's staff for ya...


Not me. Say hello to John for us, willya? :-)

The way you are posing your interpretation of this is risky. I ask you; How
big is a point? If you answer 'infinitely small', then I ask; 'How is it
possible to construct anything out of points, then?" Certainly the
one-dimensionality of points and the existance of 2- and 3-dimensional
objects constructed of points are not exclusive. Math exists, life goes on,
and you get to remain a Republican.

--riverman



Wolfgang November 2nd, 2006 04:03 PM

What's a boy to do?
 

wrote in message
...
On 1 Nov 2006 16:46:23 -0800, "Wolfgang" wrote:

SNI-I-I-I-IP

I will simply confine myself


Well, no, you didn't do either, but perhaps you should...

to making a proposition open to
anyone. Give me three darts and a prediction of where they will land
relative to one another in terms of distance from the center of the
target, and I will prove you wrong EVERY time. :)


Gee, it seems like this might be an attempt at a sucker bet...OK. I
accept. And I'd offer that you couldn't even do it ONE time... and that
you couldn't do it even if given a 3-dimensional "dartboard"...but don't
pee all over yourself, here's another hint: the taxpayers of Olathe,
Kansas are probably very glad you can't do it even that one time...why,
heck, one might say that's the essence of an industry...

HTH,
R
...I feel generous, here's another hint: ya better go back to sucker-bet
development school - with the "bet" above, it doesn't matter how, when,
or if you throw them...


The beauty of saying nothing is that you can never be proved wrong and that
you never have to retract a statement, ainna? One can only suppose that
someone suggested this strategy to you and that you stick to it without a
hint as to its efficacy out of sheer dogged inability to think of anything
else to do. Well, that and the fact that so many play so gently with you.
:)

Wolfgang
who, it must be admitted, has always been a bit rougher with his toys than
the other kids.



Ken Fortenberry November 2nd, 2006 04:10 PM

What's a boy to do?
 
Scott Seidman wrote:
...
You could ask your question in a different way, to get the answer you
want, which is "you are going to throw three darts at a target. What is
the probability that the third dart will miss by more than the first
dart?" This is a VERY different question, but the answer is the one you
are describing.


Exactly correct. Good luck trying to convince the roffian gaggle. ;-)

--
Ken Fortenberry

riverman November 2nd, 2006 04:29 PM

What's a boy to do?
 

"Jonathan Cook" wrote in message
...
Scott Seidman wrote:

You could ask your question in a different way, to get the answer you
want, which is "you are going to throw three darts at a target. What is
the probability that the third dart will miss by more than the first
dart?" This is a VERY different question, but the answer is the one you
are describing.


Yep.

I would agree that the probability above is 1/3 if you added the conditional
'given that the second dart missed by more than the first'. Otherwise, I'm
inclined (but not convinced) that the probability above is 1/2.

Since the outcome of the second dart is not taken into account, your
question is identical to 'you throw a dart, watch some TV and eat lunch,
then throw another. Whats the probability that the second is closer than the
first?' Where I am unsure is because of the existance of the middle dart...I
have to think that through more.

But I am certain that if you add that conditional, then you have my
question, with a probability of 1/3.

--riverman





Wayne Harrison November 2nd, 2006 04:36 PM

choc tr
 

"Charlie Choc" wrote

hey, duc, let us know when you post some images, either at your place or
ab.--you are coming along well, for a digiboy.

:)
yfitons
wayno



Kevin Vang November 2nd, 2006 04:38 PM

What's a boy to do?
 
In article ,
says...
According to your theory, that dart can easily
and readily strike any point on the disk or any point outside of the
circumference created by the selection of the first and second points,
up to and including "un-measurably" close to the inside or the outside
of the circumference, but can never actually strike a point on the
circumference. IOW, the third point (Dart C) can only create a second
radius that must be less than or greater than the first radius. With
not being able to select a second point on the circumference, arcs, in
such a world, don't exist. If arcs don't exist, geometry, trig, etc.
begins to break down. In the failure cascade of interrelated bits , it
takes all math down with it.



It's not that the arc doesn't exist, and we cannot choose points on
that arc. The point is that the probability of hitting that arc with
a dart is 0.

Intuitive explanation: Suppose your dartboard has radius 1. Throw a
dart at the dartboard, and let r1 = radius from the center of the
dartboard to the dart. Now throw a second dart, and let r be the
radius. Then the probability that r = r1 is

number of values of r for which r = r1 1
------------------------------------------- = ------------ = 0.
number of possible values for r infinity


More technical (and more correct) explanation: If we assume that every
point on the dartboard is equally likely to be hit, then the probability
that r = r1 is:

measure of the set for which r = r1 0
-------------------------------------- = ------------ = 0
measure of the dartboard pi * 1^2

because the dartboard is a 2-dimensional surface, the appropriate
measure is area. The measure of the entire dartboard is the area of
a circle with radius 1, so the area is pi*1^2 = 1. The set of points
for which r = r1 is the circle with radius r1. Since the circle is
just a curve with width 0 on the plane, it has area 0.

Slightly more technical (and more correct): Not every point on the
dartboard is equally likely to be hit. If p(r,theta) is the
probablility density function giving the probability that the dart hits
point (r,theta) in polar coordinates, then the probability that r = r1
is:

/ r1
| p(r,theta) dA
/ r1 0
------------------------- = --- = 0
/ 1 1
| p(r,theta) dA
/ 0

because we are integrating with respect to area, and the top integral
is done over a region with area 0, so the value of the integral is 0.


HTH,
Kevin
And I'm pretty certain that mathematics doesn't all disappear if
somebody doesn't understand one bit of it.
--
reply to: kevin dot vang at minotstateu dot edu

[email protected] November 2nd, 2006 05:23 PM

What's a boy to do?
 
On Thu, 2 Nov 2006 23:37:44 +0800, "riverman" wrote:


wrote in message
.. .
On 1 Nov 2006 16:27:51 -0800, "riverman" wrote:


Whether or not _you_ can measure to _your_ satisfaction that two points
on a 2-dimensional plane are _absolutely_ the same distance from an
initially-chosen point (in this case, a "target"_), those two points
certainly exist.


Yes, they do.

The random selection of a second point (the landing of
Dart A) "x" distance from the first point (the "target") creates a
radius from which a circumference may be scribed. The second dart (Dart
B) and its landing point have no relevance and can be ignored.


Not necessarily, it depends on what is being asked. "Conditional
probabilities" do exist. But in the case of what you are discussing (the
existance of arcs), I concur; we can ignore the second dart for now.


Well, I guess it's good that at least some of the time, you don't argue
with yourself...

A third
dart is thrown (Dart C). According to your theory, that dart can easily
and readily strike any point on the disk or any point outside of the
circumference created by the selection of the first and second points,
up to and including "un-measurably" close to the inside or the outside
of the circumference, but can never actually strike a point on the
circumference. IOW, the third point (Dart C) can only create a second
radius that must be less than or greater than the first radius.


Yes, that's correct also. There is a statement in calculus that asserts that
no matter what two numbers you choose on the number line, there is always
another number between them. No matter how close to the circumference you
get, you can always get closer. But you cannot get there unless you, well,
get there.


Oh, geez...if there's a statement and all...well, anyone thinking about
math better cut it out...just think of all the books that'll need to be
changed if someone ****s up and comes up with something new...

With
not being able to select a second point on the circumference, arcs, in
such a world, don't exist.


No one said you cannot select a second point. What is being said is that the
probability of another dart hitting that point, or any other point on that
circle, is zero. Thats because the point is infinitely small. The
probability of hitting something infinitely small is infinitely
small....zero, in fact.


Infinitely small is not "zero." One can choose to "round it off" and
just call it "zero," but it isn't, in fact, non-existent.

Here's another hint: consider the points in a tangent to point/Dart A
and the points in lines perpendicular to that tangent and...why, shoot,
sooner or later, one might account for all the points in the plane, and
then, uh-oh...

HTH,
R

Charlie Choc November 2nd, 2006 05:33 PM

choc tr
 
On Thu, 2 Nov 2006 11:36:05 -0500, "Wayne Harrison" wrote:


"Charlie Choc" wrote

hey, duc, let us know when you post some images, either at your place or
ab.--you are coming along well, for a digiboy.

:)


There are some new ones on my web site now in the Arches, Grand Teton and
Yellowstone folders, but I've got more shots that I haven't 'processed' yet.
--
Charlie...
http://www.chocphoto.com

[email protected] November 2nd, 2006 05:53 PM

What's a boy to do?
 
On Thu, 2 Nov 2006 10:38:41 -0600, Kevin Vang wrote:

In article ,
says...
According to your theory, that dart can easily
and readily strike any point on the disk or any point outside of the
circumference created by the selection of the first and second points,
up to and including "un-measurably" close to the inside or the outside
of the circumference, but can never actually strike a point on the
circumference. IOW, the third point (Dart C) can only create a second
radius that must be less than or greater than the first radius. With
not being able to select a second point on the circumference, arcs, in
such a world, don't exist. If arcs don't exist, geometry, trig, etc.
begins to break down. In the failure cascade of interrelated bits , it
takes all math down with it.



It's not that the arc doesn't exist, and we cannot choose points on
that arc. The point is that the probability of hitting that arc with
a dart is 0.

Intuitive explanation: Suppose your dartboard has radius 1. Throw a
dart at the dartboard, and let r1 = radius from the center of the
dartboard to the dart. Now throw a second dart, and let r be the
radius. Then the probability that r = r1 is

number of values of r for which r = r1 1
------------------------------------------- = ------------ = 0.
number of possible values for r infinity


More technical (and more correct) explanation: If we assume that every
point on the dartboard is equally likely to be hit, then the probability
that r = r1 is:

measure of the set for which r = r1 0
-------------------------------------- = ------------ = 0
measure of the dartboard pi * 1^2

because the dartboard is a 2-dimensional surface, the appropriate
measure is area. The measure of the entire dartboard is the area of
a circle with radius 1, so the area is pi*1^2 = 1. The set of points
for which r = r1 is the circle with radius r1. Since the circle is
just a curve with width 0 on the plane, it has area 0.

Slightly more technical (and more correct): Not every point on the
dartboard is equally likely to be hit.


Apparently. The word on the street is that at least some are completely
unhittable, what with the probability of doing so being zero or
infinitely small or pi-r-square or, well, something all dangerously full
of symbols and greek letters and ****...

If p(r,theta) is the
probablility density function giving the probability that the dart hits
point (r,theta) in polar coordinates, then the probability that r = r1
is:

/ r1
| p(r,theta) dA
/ r1 0
------------------------- = --- = 0
/ 1 1
| p(r,theta) dA
/ 0

because we are integrating with respect to area, and the top integral
is done over a region with area 0, so the value of the integral is 0.


SEE! SEE! I WARNED YA, BUT NOO-O-O-O-O...

IAC, three answers, each "and more correct" than the previous one.
Interesting. Is this progression going to lead to something infinitely
correct (or something to at least stick a fork in and call "done"), or
is the probability of hitting that target zero, too?


HTH,
Kevin
And I'm pretty certain that mathematics doesn't all disappear if
somebody doesn't understand one bit of it.


Hey, go easy on me, I'm learning...for example, I've already learned
that when 2 math whiz-types and a rat-gutter answer a question, the odds
that they will come up with the correct answer is like one in a
gazillion or bazillion or some other REALLY big ol' number...

And right back at ya, Pythagoras
R

[email protected] November 2nd, 2006 05:58 PM

What's a boy to do?
 
On Thu, 2 Nov 2006 10:03:10 -0600, "Wolfgang" wrote:


wrote in message
.. .
On 1 Nov 2006 16:46:23 -0800, "Wolfgang" wrote:

SNI-I-I-I-IP

I will simply confine myself


Well, no, you didn't do either, but perhaps you should...

to making a proposition open to
anyone. Give me three darts and a prediction of where they will land
relative to one another in terms of distance from the center of the
target, and I will prove you wrong EVERY time. :)


Gee, it seems like this might be an attempt at a sucker bet...OK. I
accept. And I'd offer that you couldn't even do it ONE time... and that
you couldn't do it even if given a 3-dimensional "dartboard"...but don't
pee all over yourself, here's another hint: the taxpayers of Olathe,
Kansas are probably very glad you can't do it even that one time...why,
heck, one might say that's the essence of an industry...

HTH,
R
...I feel generous, here's another hint: ya better go back to sucker-bet
development school - with the "bet" above, it doesn't matter how, when,
or if you throw them...


The beauty of saying nothing is that you can never be proved wrong and that
you never have to retract a statement, ainna? One can only suppose that
someone suggested this strategy to you and that you stick to it without a
hint as to its efficacy out of sheer dogged inability to think of anything
else to do. Well, that and the fact that so many play so gently with you.
:)


Hee, hee, hee...

Again, I accept your proposal...wanna bet on the outcome?

Wolfgang
who, it must be admitted, has always been a bit rougher with his toys than
the other kids.


Hmmm...maybe a big handful of Albolene would cut down on the
irritation...

While from a humanity standpoint I hope that helps, from a
keeping-down-lunch standpoint, I don't care to know if it did,
R

Calif Bill November 2nd, 2006 06:14 PM

What's a boy to do?
 

"riverman" wrote in message
oups.com...

Calif Bill wrote:
"Kevin Vang" wrote in message
t...
In article t,
says...
Your statement was no two darts could land equidistant from the
center.
As
I state, totally wrong.


Two darts could conceivable land equidistant from the center; however,
the probability of that happening is 0. Explaining why will require a
bit of less than elementary probability theory, with integral calculus
as a prerequisite. We can go there, if you are up to it...

Kevin


Explain why could not happen.


I don't know if you have taken Integral Calculus, so I won't use that
to explain it. The simplest 'geometrically appealing' explanation is to
say that the probability of hitting some target is directly related to
the size of the target. The bigger the spot you are trying to hit, the
more likely it is to hit it.

Now, if you are aiming for a curved line....specifically the line that
describes a circle, you have to consider the width of that line. Since
circles are a collection of points, and points have no width, then you
are essentially aiming for something that has a width of zero. Which
means the possibility of hitting it is zero.

You can hit it ONCE, because its position is unknown until the first
dart actually lands. Once that dart establishes the position of the
circle, it becomes a target of width zero which another dart cannot
possibly hit. You can reduce the size of your miss (lets call it your
'slop') to be as small as you want by making less and less precise
measurements, but the converse is also true...you can always find the
slop by increasing the precision of your measurement. You cannot
eliminate the slop; you cannot ever hit the line.: its a matter of
precision. Just like no two snowflakes are alike.

Throwing more and more darts DOES increase the liklihood of hitting
something more than once, but if the liklihood of hitting it is already
infinitely small; throwing more and more darts doesn't make it any more
likely. Throwing infinite darts creates what is called an
'indeterminate' form, and we cannot solve it that way. We get an
infinitely large number of opportunities of achieving something that
has an infinitely small chance of happening. Its incorrect to conclude
that it will happen infinite times....Infinity x (1/infinity) does not
equal infinity. It doesn't equal, or mean, anything.

However, throwing a FINITE number of darts....say two, at something
that we have an infintely small chance of hitting IS solvable. Its
three times 'infinitely small', which is still 'infinitely small'. If
you have taken any calculus, you know the value of 'infintely small' is
zero.

--riverman


Actually I have taken integral calculus and am a retired engineer and signal
processing engineer. Using your analogy that the point is infinitely small
and therefore non-existent, then the first dart could not hit a point
either. And would not be in existence. Your supposition that there could
never be another dart at the same exact distance fails obviously. Reminds
me of the old story about the difference between a mathematician and an
engineer.
The two are on the football field goal line and on the other goal line is
the best of the Dallas cheerleaders, buck naked. The mathman and the
engineer are told the first person that gets there gets to do any thing they
desire with the lassie. Only rule is you can only move 1/2 the distance to
the goal in any one move. The mathman says no use to start as it is an
infinite series and you will never get there. The engineer, says 8 moves
and I can be close enough for my purposes.



Kevin Vang November 2nd, 2006 06:27 PM

What's a boy to do?
 
In article t,
says...
The two are on the football field goal line and on the other goal line is
the best of the Dallas cheerleaders, buck naked. The mathman and the
engineer are told the first person that gets there gets to do any thing they
desire with the lassie. Only rule is you can only move 1/2 the distance to
the goal in any one move. The mathman says no use to start as it is an
infinite series and you will never get there. The engineer, says 8 moves
and I can be close enough for my purposes.



Then "mathman" clearly didn't know what he was talking about. I do this
in my Calc II class every year when we get to the chapter on infinite
series. I don't have any nekkid cheerleaders, but I stand at one wall
and tell the class I plan to walk half of the distance to the other
wall, then walk half of the remaining difference, then walk half the
remaining difference, and so on. I ask "Will I make it to the other
wall?" I ask for a show of hands, and most students raise their hands
for "No". Then I say, "Watch me," and walk directly across the room
until I bump into the far wall. Lively discussion then ensues...

Kevin

--
reply to: kevin dot vang at minotstateu dot edu

riverman November 2nd, 2006 06:46 PM

What's a boy to do?
 

"Calif Bill" wrote in message
k.net...

"riverman" wrote in message
oups.com...

Actually I have taken integral calculus and am a retired engineer and
signal processing engineer. Using your analogy that the point is
infinitely small and therefore non-existent, then the first dart could not
hit a point either. And would not be in existence.


Ummm, I never said it was my analogy. Its part of the definition of a point,
and has been around since Euclid. Points are infinitely small 1-dimensional
objects; no one said they were non-existant. I said the probability of
hitting a point on a defined arc is zero. This can be proven with
theoretical math, or intuitively defended as a matter of precision in
measurement.

Like Kevin, I go through this with my own AB and BC Calculus and Honors
Precalculus students yearly, and have for 14 years. And like his story of
approaching the wall, I use Zeno's paradox about Achilles and the tortoise
to show the dangers of trying to solve problems using indeterminate forms.

Your supposition that there could never be another dart at the same exact
distance fails obviously. Reminds me of the old story about the difference
between a mathematician and an engineer.


LOL. Even without the myriad of stories, your use of 'obviously' underscores
the difference between mathematicians and engineers. :-)

--riverman



Wolfgang November 2nd, 2006 06:51 PM

What's a boy to do?
 

"Calif Bill" wrote in message
k.net...

...the difference between a mathematician and an engineer....


Mathematicians don't (usually) get a license to kill and they are (usually)
guilty of a passing familiarity with numbers and stuff like that.

Wolfgang




All times are GMT +1. The time now is 03:50 PM.

Powered by vBulletin® Version 3.6.4
Copyright ©2000 - 2025, Jelsoft Enterprises Ltd.
Copyright ©2004 - 2006 FishingBanter