![]() |
What's a boy to do?
On 30 Oct 2006 16:17:56 -0800, "riverman" wrote:
First, list all the ways to throw three darts, A B and C. ABC ACB BAC BCA CAB CBA Those aren't all the ways...think about it. Remember, we are looking at a conditional probability; dart B has already landed farther than dart A. So our list of outcomes is limited to: ABC ACB CAB No, it isn't...think about it. Our 'definition of success' is when dart C lands further than dart A, which is clearly only the first two arrangements. So the probability of throwing a third dart that lands farther than the first (given the second dart has already landed farther than the first), is 2/3. Its an unsettling conclusion, because people want to make the argument that the distance from the bullseye affects the probability of each outcome. Well, perhaps it's because of that, or perhaps because it's wrong...think about it. However, every possible distance affects every outcome equally, so they are all still equally likely, as counterintuitive as it may be. Maybe it would help you get on-target answer-wise if you tied a string to your finger in exactly the same spot two days in a row... HTH, R --riverman |
What's a boy to do?
riverman wrote:
Its an unsettling conclusion, because people want to make the argument that the distance from the bullseye affects the probability of each outcome. However, every possible distance affects every outcome equally, so they are all still equally likely, as counterintuitive as it may be. I agree with the basic premise and conclusions as you present them; but I have to disagree that the six original possibilities are equally possible as the original problem is stated. If all three darts are thrown at the same time, and the probabilities are computed based on the final position of the three darts, then I agree. But if the darts are thrown sequentially, and with the implied effects of skill and intent (and OBROFF, sobriety), then I'm unconvinced that the outcomes are equally random. I like the parallels of this question with the MH paradox. The intuitive answer for an individual case is different than the mathematical answer for a large sample size. I suppose that's what makes them interesting. Joe F. |
What's a boy to do?
"Jonathan Cook" wrote in message ... Wolfgang wrote: An interesting problem was recently brought to my attention. I think I've seen this before but never really thought about it. Thanks. I like you so I'm going to make this easier for you," and I remove board number three to show you that it has a "you lose" tag under it. Obviously, the five dollars must be under one of the other two. "So," I say, "would you like to stick with your original pick, or change your mind?" It is a given that the game is not rigged in any way and you are not being fooled by anything ambiguous or otherwise misleading in the description. The question.......what should you do? I agree with everything that's been written here on what the "correct" solution is, and how Marilyn made a bunch of PhDs and professors look stupid (not that hard, really), but the problem has been irking me, and I finally decided why. You posed the problem _singularly_. One try. Probability is about expected outcomes over lots of attempts. It breaks down in a singular event. Expermental probability is about expected outcomes observed over multiple attempts, while theoretical probability is about expected outcomes calculated by counting possible outcomes. But Probabilities in general ARE about predicted outcomes for singular events. As a _singular_ event, you either have the right board or not, there is no "law of averages" to consider. And singularly, I'm not convinced that it is worth switching boards (though I absolutely agree that over lots of tries it is). Put the numbers 1-100 in a hat, and draw one. It could be #1, or it might not. It is correct to say that, the probability of it being #1 is 1/100 based on 100 draws, but as a singular event, its either #1 or its not. But those two outcomes (that it is or its not) aren't equally likely. Its far more likely to be something other than #1, so if I drew a number and said "want to bet a horse that it's #1", you'd refuse the bet, because the probabilities are well against you. Think of it this way. What if you randomly turned over one of the remaining boards, and when the board had "you lose" on it, you offered to let me switch with the other one. Should I? Obviously in this case it doesn't matter, because I still lose on the times the board with the money is turned over, so switching or not I'll only win, on average, 50% of the remaining ones, which is 1/3 of all of them. Randomness doesn't add information to the problem like purposely turning over the losing board does. But suppose I just play the game once, and the random turnover displays a "you lose" board. Then it looks just like your "play once" scenario. If we RANDOMLY turned over a board, then it would be the winning board 1/3 of the time. In that case, you have a 0% chance of winning no matter what you do. If the board we randomly turned over was a losing board, then you'd have a 50% chance of winning by staying or switching. If the original problem said 'you pick a board, then Wolfie randomly turns over another board and it says 'you lose', then you might as well keep your original choice. But that's not the problem being stated. Monty Hall (or Wolfgang, in this case) is not RANDOMLY turning over a board: he knows the winning board and he does NOT turn that over. Its not random, so not only does randomness not add info to the problem, it doesn't even apply. Probability is not the right analysis for a singular event. At least that's what I think now, and now I'm going to bed...maybe I'll be wrong in the morning ;-) Yes, you will be. Sorry. :-) --riverman |
What's a boy to do?
wrote in message ... On 30 Oct 2006 16:17:56 -0800, "riverman" wrote: First, list all the ways to throw three darts, A B and C. ABC ACB BAC BCA CAB CBA Those aren't all the ways...think about it. Remember, we are looking at a conditional probability; dart B has already landed farther than dart A. So our list of outcomes is limited to: ABC ACB CAB No, it isn't...think about it. Our 'definition of success' is when dart C lands further than dart A, which is clearly only the first two arrangements. So the probability of throwing a third dart that lands farther than the first (given the second dart has already landed farther than the first), is 2/3. Its an unsettling conclusion, because people want to make the argument that the distance from the bullseye affects the probability of each outcome. Well, perhaps it's because of that, or perhaps because it's wrong...think about it. However, every possible distance affects every outcome equally, so they are all still equally likely, as counterintuitive as it may be. Maybe it would help you get on-target answer-wise if you tied a string to your finger in exactly the same spot two days in a row... Thats not possible. --riverman |
What's a boy to do?
On Oct 27, 12:40 pm, "Wolfgang" wrote: An interesting problem was recently brought to my attention. Let us say that you and I are standing next to a table on which I have placed three boards identical in every respect except that each has a different number painted on it.....1, 2, and 3, respectively. I say to you that if you turn your back I will place a five dollar bill under one of the boards and a slip of paper that says "you lose" under each of the others. You then turn back to face the table and point to or name the board you think has the five dollar bill under it. If you're right, you win the five bucks. We proceed. You pick, say, board number one. I say, "O.k., tell you what, I like you so I'm going to make this easier for you," and I remove board number three to show you that it has a "you lose" tag under it. Obviously, the five dollars must be under one of the other two. "So," I say, "would you like to stick with your original pick, or change your mind?" It is a given that the game is not rigged in any way and you are not being fooled by anything ambiguous or otherwise misleading in the description. The question.......what should you do? Wolfgang It don't matter. Play the game 300 times and you win 100 no matter how you do it. Initially your chances are 1/3. With the give away the chances are expressed (1/2)*(2/3), which is 1/3 same as above. Again if you play 300 times you win 100. If I remember correctly Poission figured all this out working for a wealthy French nobelman who loved to gamble. |
What's a boy to do?
Jonathan Cook wrote: Wolfgang wrote: An interesting problem was recently brought to my attention. I think I've seen this before but never really thought about it. Thanks. You're welcome. I like you so I'm going to make this easier for you," and I remove board number three to show you that it has a "you lose" tag under it. Obviously, the five dollars must be under one of the other two. "So," I say, "would you like to stick with your original pick, or change your mind?" It is a given that the game is not rigged in any way and you are not being fooled by anything ambiguous or otherwise misleading in the description. The question.......what should you do? I agree with everything that's been written here on what the "correct" solution is, and how Marilyn made a bunch of PhDs and professors look stupid (not that hard, really), I'll risk belaboring a point here because I believe it is an important one. Ms. Savant did NOT make anyone look stupid. I think she was certainly aware that many people would immediately jump to the wrong conclusion.....else, why bother with what is in the final analysis a very simple problem in mathematics? The whole point of the exercise is that the answer IS counterintuitive. What made people look stupid wasn't coming up with the wrong answer which was (and is) after all something akin to falling into the trap of trying to figure out the answer the question of where to bury the survivors of a plane crash that occurs smack dab on an international border. What makes people look stupid is insisting on the wrong answer after the correct (and simple) one has been revealed and explained. Well, that and, in this instance, Haddon's nasty little bias trick. I get to keep my shiny new nickel because no one noticed.....or at least no one pointed out.....that all of the outraged authors of the quotes he used were associated with an institution of higher learning, 5 of 6 were identified as Ph.D.s, and several references were made to mathematics and mathematicians while none of the authors was identified as such. I have a hard time believing that this is a representative sample of all the letters sent to Ms. Savant in response to her exposition of the Monty Hall problem. but the problem has been irking me, and I finally decided why. You posed the problem _singularly_. One try. Probability is about expected outcomes over lots of attempts. It breaks down in a singular event. As a _singular_ event, you either have the right board or not, there is no "law of averages" to consider. And singularly, I'm not convinced that it is worth switching boards (though I absolutely agree that over lots of tries it is). The trouble here is at least partially one of semantics (I cannot for the life of me understand why semantics is so widely accepted as a pejorative term.....but that's another rant altogether). Playing the game once constitutes a "single" event, not a "singular" one in any meaningful sense. The difference is critical. A singular event is something that happens only once......something like the evolution of life on Earth, to pick a particularly controversial example. Playing the game once may APPEAR to be singular if one stresses all the details about who is involved, what they are wearing today, what they had for breakfast etc. but, in all its essentials, it is identical to millions of other events. It is NOT singular. The laws of probabilities apply......MUST apply......not because this particular avatar is repeated, but because it is repeatable and myriad others like it in every essential detail have been repeated often enough for the mathematically derived probabilities to be confirmed experimentally. At any rate, you DO believe that probabilities apply to single events and I can prove it easily. All we have to do is raise the stakes......we don't even need to calculate the odds with any precision. You are in a large airplane of a type famous for its ability to glide like a brick, and the engines fail. You have a parachute. You have never used a parachute before. I think we may take it as a given that you are not likely to repeat the experiment......and your internet connection is too slow for Google be of much use in finding someone else who has. What do you do......jump?.....or ride it out? Think of it this way. What if you randomly turned over one of the remaining boards, and when the board had "you lose" on it, you offered to let me switch with the other one. Should I? Yes, absolutely. Despite the fact that introducing a random element has entirely changed the nature of the problem, as long as the random pick turns up a loser, the outcome is identical to that of the original. Changing your pick doubles the odds of winning. Obviously in this case it doesn't matter, because I still lose on the times the board with the money is turned over, so switching or not I'll only win, on average, 50% of the remaining ones, which is 1/3 of all of them. Randomness doesn't add information to the problem like purposely turning over the losing board does. But suppose I just play the game once, and the random turnover displays a "you lose" board. Then it looks just like your "play once" scenario. Probability is not the right analysis for a singular event. At least that's what I think now, and now I'm going to bed...maybe I'll be wrong in the morning ;-) Jon. |
What's a boy to do?
Wolfgang wrote: Jonathan Cook wrote: .... Think of it this way. What if you randomly turned over one of the remaining boards, and when the board had "you lose" on it, you offered to let me switch with the other one. Should I? Yes, absolutely. Despite the fact that introducing a random element has entirely changed the nature of the problem, as long as the random pick turns up a loser, the outcome is identical to that of the original. Changing your pick doubles the odds of winning. There was supposed to be more to this......yeah, I know, just what everybody wanted to hear! :) I'm still not used to posting on Google. Hit the "post message" button too soon. Will try again with the whole thing (I hope) shortly. Wolfgang |
What's a boy to do?
Jonathan Cook wrote: Wolfgang wrote: An interesting problem was recently brought to my attention. I think I've seen this before but never really thought about it. Thanks. You're welcome. I like you so I'm going to make this easier for you," and I remove board number three to show you that it has a "you lose" tag under it. Obviously, the five dollars must be under one of the other two. "So," I say, "would you like to stick with your original pick, or change your mind?" It is a given that the game is not rigged in any way and you are not being fooled by anything ambiguous or otherwise misleading in the description. The question.......what should you do? I agree with everything that's been written here on what the "correct" solution is, and how Marilyn made a bunch of PhDs and professors look stupid (not that hard, really), I'll risk belaboring a point here because I believe it is an important one. Ms. Savant did NOT make anyone look stupid. I think she was certainly aware that many people would immediately jump to the wrong conclusion.....else, why bother with what is in the final analysis a very simple problem in mathematics? The whole point of the exercise is that the answer IS counterintuitive. What made people look stupid wasn't coming up with the wrong answer which was (and is) after all something akin to falling into the trap of trying to figure out the answer the question of where to bury the survivors of a plane crash that occurs smack dab on an international border. What makes people look stupid is insisting on the wrong answer after the correct (and simple) one has been revealed and explained. Well, that and, in this instance, Haddon's nasty little bias trick. I get to keep my shiny new nickel because no one noticed.....or at least no one pointed out.....that all of the outraged authors of the quotes he used were associated with an institution of higher learning, 5 of 6 were identified as Ph.D.s, and several references were made to mathematics and mathematicians while none of the authors was identified as such. I have a hard time believing that this is a representative sample of all the letters sent to Ms. Savant in response to her exposition of the Monty Hall problem. but the problem has been irking me, and I finally decided why. You posed the problem _singularly_. One try. Probability is about expected outcomes over lots of attempts. It breaks down in a singular event. As a _singular_ event, you either have the right board or not, there is no "law of averages" to consider. And singularly, I'm not convinced that it is worth switching boards (though I absolutely agree that over lots of tries it is). The trouble here is at least partially one of semantics (I cannot for the life of me understand why semantics is so widely accepted as a pejorative term.....but that's another rant altogether). Playing the game once constitutes a "single" event, not a "singular" one in any meaningful sense. The difference is critical. A singular event is something that happens only once......something like the evolution of life on Earth, to pick a particularly controversial example. Playing the game once may APPEAR to be singular if one stresses all the details about who is involved, what they are wearing today, what they had for breakfast etc. but, in all its essentials, it is identical to millions of other events. It is NOT singular. The laws of probabilities apply......MUST apply......not because this particular avatar is repeated, but because it is repeatable and myriad others like it in every essential detail have been repeated often enough for the mathematically derived probabilities to be confirmed experimentally. At any rate, you DO believe that probabilities apply to single events and I can prove it easily. All we have to do is raise the stakes......we don't even need to calculate the odds with any precision. You are in a large airplane of a type famous for its ability to glide like a brick, and the engines fail. You have a parachute. You have never used a parachute before. I think we may take it as a given that you are not likely to repeat the experiment......and your internet connection is too slow for Google be of much use in finding someone else who has. What do you do......jump?.....or ride it out? Think of it this way. What if you randomly turned over one of the remaining boards, and when the board had "you lose" on it, you offered to let me switch with the other one. Should I? Yes, absolutely. Despite the fact that introducing a random element has entirely changed the nature of the problem, as long as the random pick turns up a loser, the outcome is identical to that of the original. Changing your pick doubles the odds of winning. Obviously in this case it doesn't matter, because I still lose on the times the board with the money is turned over, Don't look now, but you've just claimed that it doesn't matter what you do in one situation because something else might happen in a different situation. If logic counts for anything, you have just torn the fabric of the universe asunder. so switching or not I'll only win, on average, 50% of the remaining ones, which is 1/3 of all of them. O.k., I'll stipulate that your analysis of the numbers is correct. So what? All you've done devise a scenario in which the odds of winning are 50:50. This has no bearing on the original problem in which the point of the whole thing is that the odds are NOT 50:50. Randomness doesn't add information to the problem like purposely turning over the losing board does. Correct.....and it isn't adding anything to understanding or elucidating it either. But suppose I just play the game once, and the random turnover displays a "you lose" board. Then it looks just like your "play once" scenario. Sure it does. But the important thing is that it plays out like it too......it doubles the odds of winning. Probability is not the right analysis for a singular event. At least that's what I think now, and now I'm going to bed...maybe I'll be wrong in the morning ;-) Well, you're right about the utility of probabilities in predicting singular events. But you are wrong in thinking that this is what we are dealing with. Toivo and Aino are back. This time they're in Vegas and they're playing a somewhat different game. There are ten thousand boards and only one of them has a five dollar bill under it. As before, Toivo gets one pick and Aino gets the rest. They are going to play the game just one time. You don't get to play at all. You just get to bet on who is going to win. You get to bet just one time. Who are you going to bet on? Wolfgang and how much would you be willing to risk? :) o.k......that's all of it. |
What's a boy to do?
As soon as you lifted #3 and exposed it as "you lose", the problem was over. Now we have a new one: Two boards -- one with a five and one without. By asking me if I wish to change my mind, the new problem is simply one of choosing #1 or #2. I do this by saying yes or no. My probablity of getting the $5 is simply 0.5 SO, in answer to the question: "what do I do", I flip a coin. The dart problem is indeterminate -- not enough information about unstated variables. cheers oz -- there's these two trains, heading towards each other with a bee flying............ |
What's a boy to do?
MajorOz wrote: As soon as you lifted #3 and exposed it as "you lose", the problem was over. Well, not quite.....there was still the matter of making a choice.....AFTER figuring out what the best choice is. Now we have a new one: Two boards -- one with a five and one without. By asking me if I wish to change my mind, Huh? Who is asking you to change your mind about what? The scenario, as stated, gives no hint that you have done, said, or otherwise decided anything about which to change your mind. the new problem is simply one of choosing #1 or #2. Huh? What was the old problem? (um......is anybody else seeing a whole bunch of words here that aren't showing up on my screen?) I do this by saying yes or no. What are you saying "yes" or "no" to? Is it perhaps #1?.......or maybe #2?.....something invisible to mere mortals? My probablity of getting the $5 is simply 0.5 O.k........if you say so. SO, in answer to the question: "what do I do", I flip a coin. Toward what end? The dart problem is indeterminate -- not enough information about unstated variables. We await the detailed analysis with bated breath......or palpitations......or something. cheers Prosit! oz -- there's these two trains, heading towards each other with a bee flying............ Huh? Wolfgang who is beginning to think that perhaps brother skwalid has a point after all.......this universe is starting to get a disturbingly skewed look to it. :( |
All times are GMT +1. The time now is 03:54 AM. |
Powered by vBulletin® Version 3.6.4
Copyright ©2000 - 2025, Jelsoft Enterprises Ltd.
Copyright ©2004 - 2006 FishingBanter