![]() |
If this is your first visit, be sure to check out the FAQ by clicking the link above. You may have to register before you can post: click the register link above to proceed. To start viewing messages, select the forum that you want to visit from the selection below. |
|
|
Thread Tools | Display Modes |
#111
|
|||
|
|||
![]() "Charlie Choc" wrote hey, duc, let us know when you post some images, either at your place or ab.--you are coming along well, for a digiboy. ![]() yfitons wayno |
#112
|
|||
|
|||
![]() |
#113
|
|||
|
|||
![]()
On Thu, 2 Nov 2006 23:37:44 +0800, "riverman" wrote:
wrote in message .. . On 1 Nov 2006 16:27:51 -0800, "riverman" wrote: Whether or not _you_ can measure to _your_ satisfaction that two points on a 2-dimensional plane are _absolutely_ the same distance from an initially-chosen point (in this case, a "target"_), those two points certainly exist. Yes, they do. The random selection of a second point (the landing of Dart A) "x" distance from the first point (the "target") creates a radius from which a circumference may be scribed. The second dart (Dart B) and its landing point have no relevance and can be ignored. Not necessarily, it depends on what is being asked. "Conditional probabilities" do exist. But in the case of what you are discussing (the existance of arcs), I concur; we can ignore the second dart for now. Well, I guess it's good that at least some of the time, you don't argue with yourself... A third dart is thrown (Dart C). According to your theory, that dart can easily and readily strike any point on the disk or any point outside of the circumference created by the selection of the first and second points, up to and including "un-measurably" close to the inside or the outside of the circumference, but can never actually strike a point on the circumference. IOW, the third point (Dart C) can only create a second radius that must be less than or greater than the first radius. Yes, that's correct also. There is a statement in calculus that asserts that no matter what two numbers you choose on the number line, there is always another number between them. No matter how close to the circumference you get, you can always get closer. But you cannot get there unless you, well, get there. Oh, geez...if there's a statement and all...well, anyone thinking about math better cut it out...just think of all the books that'll need to be changed if someone ****s up and comes up with something new... With not being able to select a second point on the circumference, arcs, in such a world, don't exist. No one said you cannot select a second point. What is being said is that the probability of another dart hitting that point, or any other point on that circle, is zero. Thats because the point is infinitely small. The probability of hitting something infinitely small is infinitely small....zero, in fact. Infinitely small is not "zero." One can choose to "round it off" and just call it "zero," but it isn't, in fact, non-existent. Here's another hint: consider the points in a tangent to point/Dart A and the points in lines perpendicular to that tangent and...why, shoot, sooner or later, one might account for all the points in the plane, and then, uh-oh... HTH, R |
#114
|
|||
|
|||
![]()
On Thu, 2 Nov 2006 11:36:05 -0500, "Wayne Harrison" wrote:
"Charlie Choc" wrote hey, duc, let us know when you post some images, either at your place or ab.--you are coming along well, for a digiboy. ![]() There are some new ones on my web site now in the Arches, Grand Teton and Yellowstone folders, but I've got more shots that I haven't 'processed' yet. -- Charlie... http://www.chocphoto.com |
#115
|
|||
|
|||
![]()
On Thu, 2 Nov 2006 10:38:41 -0600, Kevin Vang wrote:
In article , says... According to your theory, that dart can easily and readily strike any point on the disk or any point outside of the circumference created by the selection of the first and second points, up to and including "un-measurably" close to the inside or the outside of the circumference, but can never actually strike a point on the circumference. IOW, the third point (Dart C) can only create a second radius that must be less than or greater than the first radius. With not being able to select a second point on the circumference, arcs, in such a world, don't exist. If arcs don't exist, geometry, trig, etc. begins to break down. In the failure cascade of interrelated bits , it takes all math down with it. It's not that the arc doesn't exist, and we cannot choose points on that arc. The point is that the probability of hitting that arc with a dart is 0. Intuitive explanation: Suppose your dartboard has radius 1. Throw a dart at the dartboard, and let r1 = radius from the center of the dartboard to the dart. Now throw a second dart, and let r be the radius. Then the probability that r = r1 is number of values of r for which r = r1 1 ------------------------------------------- = ------------ = 0. number of possible values for r infinity More technical (and more correct) explanation: If we assume that every point on the dartboard is equally likely to be hit, then the probability that r = r1 is: measure of the set for which r = r1 0 -------------------------------------- = ------------ = 0 measure of the dartboard pi * 1^2 because the dartboard is a 2-dimensional surface, the appropriate measure is area. The measure of the entire dartboard is the area of a circle with radius 1, so the area is pi*1^2 = 1. The set of points for which r = r1 is the circle with radius r1. Since the circle is just a curve with width 0 on the plane, it has area 0. Slightly more technical (and more correct): Not every point on the dartboard is equally likely to be hit. Apparently. The word on the street is that at least some are completely unhittable, what with the probability of doing so being zero or infinitely small or pi-r-square or, well, something all dangerously full of symbols and greek letters and ****... If p(r,theta) is the probablility density function giving the probability that the dart hits point (r,theta) in polar coordinates, then the probability that r = r1 is: / r1 | p(r,theta) dA / r1 0 ------------------------- = --- = 0 / 1 1 | p(r,theta) dA / 0 because we are integrating with respect to area, and the top integral is done over a region with area 0, so the value of the integral is 0. SEE! SEE! I WARNED YA, BUT NOO-O-O-O-O... IAC, three answers, each "and more correct" than the previous one. Interesting. Is this progression going to lead to something infinitely correct (or something to at least stick a fork in and call "done"), or is the probability of hitting that target zero, too? HTH, Kevin And I'm pretty certain that mathematics doesn't all disappear if somebody doesn't understand one bit of it. Hey, go easy on me, I'm learning...for example, I've already learned that when 2 math whiz-types and a rat-gutter answer a question, the odds that they will come up with the correct answer is like one in a gazillion or bazillion or some other REALLY big ol' number... And right back at ya, Pythagoras R |
#116
|
|||
|
|||
![]()
On Thu, 2 Nov 2006 10:03:10 -0600, "Wolfgang" wrote:
wrote in message .. . On 1 Nov 2006 16:46:23 -0800, "Wolfgang" wrote: SNI-I-I-I-IP I will simply confine myself Well, no, you didn't do either, but perhaps you should... to making a proposition open to anyone. Give me three darts and a prediction of where they will land relative to one another in terms of distance from the center of the target, and I will prove you wrong EVERY time. ![]() Gee, it seems like this might be an attempt at a sucker bet...OK. I accept. And I'd offer that you couldn't even do it ONE time... and that you couldn't do it even if given a 3-dimensional "dartboard"...but don't pee all over yourself, here's another hint: the taxpayers of Olathe, Kansas are probably very glad you can't do it even that one time...why, heck, one might say that's the essence of an industry... HTH, R ...I feel generous, here's another hint: ya better go back to sucker-bet development school - with the "bet" above, it doesn't matter how, when, or if you throw them... The beauty of saying nothing is that you can never be proved wrong and that you never have to retract a statement, ainna? One can only suppose that someone suggested this strategy to you and that you stick to it without a hint as to its efficacy out of sheer dogged inability to think of anything else to do. Well, that and the fact that so many play so gently with you. ![]() Hee, hee, hee... Again, I accept your proposal...wanna bet on the outcome? Wolfgang who, it must be admitted, has always been a bit rougher with his toys than the other kids. Hmmm...maybe a big handful of Albolene would cut down on the irritation... While from a humanity standpoint I hope that helps, from a keeping-down-lunch standpoint, I don't care to know if it did, R |
#117
|
|||
|
|||
![]() "riverman" wrote in message oups.com... Calif Bill wrote: "Kevin Vang" wrote in message t... In article t, says... Your statement was no two darts could land equidistant from the center. As I state, totally wrong. Two darts could conceivable land equidistant from the center; however, the probability of that happening is 0. Explaining why will require a bit of less than elementary probability theory, with integral calculus as a prerequisite. We can go there, if you are up to it... Kevin Explain why could not happen. I don't know if you have taken Integral Calculus, so I won't use that to explain it. The simplest 'geometrically appealing' explanation is to say that the probability of hitting some target is directly related to the size of the target. The bigger the spot you are trying to hit, the more likely it is to hit it. Now, if you are aiming for a curved line....specifically the line that describes a circle, you have to consider the width of that line. Since circles are a collection of points, and points have no width, then you are essentially aiming for something that has a width of zero. Which means the possibility of hitting it is zero. You can hit it ONCE, because its position is unknown until the first dart actually lands. Once that dart establishes the position of the circle, it becomes a target of width zero which another dart cannot possibly hit. You can reduce the size of your miss (lets call it your 'slop') to be as small as you want by making less and less precise measurements, but the converse is also true...you can always find the slop by increasing the precision of your measurement. You cannot eliminate the slop; you cannot ever hit the line.: its a matter of precision. Just like no two snowflakes are alike. Throwing more and more darts DOES increase the liklihood of hitting something more than once, but if the liklihood of hitting it is already infinitely small; throwing more and more darts doesn't make it any more likely. Throwing infinite darts creates what is called an 'indeterminate' form, and we cannot solve it that way. We get an infinitely large number of opportunities of achieving something that has an infinitely small chance of happening. Its incorrect to conclude that it will happen infinite times....Infinity x (1/infinity) does not equal infinity. It doesn't equal, or mean, anything. However, throwing a FINITE number of darts....say two, at something that we have an infintely small chance of hitting IS solvable. Its three times 'infinitely small', which is still 'infinitely small'. If you have taken any calculus, you know the value of 'infintely small' is zero. --riverman Actually I have taken integral calculus and am a retired engineer and signal processing engineer. Using your analogy that the point is infinitely small and therefore non-existent, then the first dart could not hit a point either. And would not be in existence. Your supposition that there could never be another dart at the same exact distance fails obviously. Reminds me of the old story about the difference between a mathematician and an engineer. The two are on the football field goal line and on the other goal line is the best of the Dallas cheerleaders, buck naked. The mathman and the engineer are told the first person that gets there gets to do any thing they desire with the lassie. Only rule is you can only move 1/2 the distance to the goal in any one move. The mathman says no use to start as it is an infinite series and you will never get there. The engineer, says 8 moves and I can be close enough for my purposes. |
#118
|
|||
|
|||
![]() |
#119
|
|||
|
|||
![]() "Calif Bill" wrote in message k.net... "riverman" wrote in message oups.com... Actually I have taken integral calculus and am a retired engineer and signal processing engineer. Using your analogy that the point is infinitely small and therefore non-existent, then the first dart could not hit a point either. And would not be in existence. Ummm, I never said it was my analogy. Its part of the definition of a point, and has been around since Euclid. Points are infinitely small 1-dimensional objects; no one said they were non-existant. I said the probability of hitting a point on a defined arc is zero. This can be proven with theoretical math, or intuitively defended as a matter of precision in measurement. Like Kevin, I go through this with my own AB and BC Calculus and Honors Precalculus students yearly, and have for 14 years. And like his story of approaching the wall, I use Zeno's paradox about Achilles and the tortoise to show the dangers of trying to solve problems using indeterminate forms. Your supposition that there could never be another dart at the same exact distance fails obviously. Reminds me of the old story about the difference between a mathematician and an engineer. LOL. Even without the myriad of stories, your use of 'obviously' underscores the difference between mathematicians and engineers. :-) --riverman |
#120
|
|||
|
|||
![]() "Calif Bill" wrote in message k.net... ...the difference between a mathematician and an engineer.... Mathematicians don't (usually) get a license to kill and they are (usually) guilty of a passing familiarity with numbers and stuff like that. Wolfgang |
Thread Tools | |
Display Modes | |
|
|